Sound symbolism is not a very satisfactory term but it is a familiar one
to cover a phenomenon which has been noted and studied over very many years,
the apparent appropriateness of the sound-structures of many individual words
for their meanings. A better description for this might be 'natural
expressiveness'. What is unsatisfactory about the term 'sound symbolism' is
its use of the radically confused concept 'symbol'. This is one of the words
used extensively and with confidence in many different disciplines, but with
no clear idea of what a 'symbol' is. Often there is total contradiction
between the use of 'symbol' by different authors. So, Peterfalvi (1970),
author of perhaps the best book in French on sound symbolism (commended warmly
by Roman Jakobson 1987), says that the term 'symbol' in its modern sense
always includes the idea of a natural, and not conventional, analogical
correspondence between the concrete form and the object which it symbolises.
Bolinger(1963), a leading American linguist, takes the radically opposite
view: meanings in which form imitates nature are called iconic: meanings that
are arbitrary and conventional are called symbolic. A clash of symbols indeed!
More serious than the right name for the phenomenon of 'sound symbolism'
is the cast-iron orthodoxy formulated by leading authorities in linguistics
that the phenomenon does not exist at all. Saussure (1915) is notorious for
the slogan 'l'arbitraire du signe', by which he denied onomatopoeia (and all
other natural expressiveness of words) other than as marginal, and treated
even apparent onomatopoeic words as no more than conventionalised forms. This
dogma was restated and reinforced by Charles Hockett(1958, 1963) in his
influential identification of what he described as 'design features' of
language: The relation between a meaningful element in language and its
denotation is independent of any physical and geometrical resemblance between
the two. The semantic relation is arbitrary rather than iconic.. Other
influential linguists concurred; Firth(1964) warned students to beware of
sound symbolism, saying that the sounds of words in themselves paint nothing.
This certainty on the part of Saussure and his followers is all the more
surprising and apparently perverse in the face of the exceptionally long
history of evidence to the contrary, presented by equally perceptive and
equally authoritative writers, and in the face of what has in this century
become the large body of scientifically planned experiment establishing the
reality of sound symbolism. The debate started with Plato (in the dialogue
Cratylus):"Everything has a right name of its own, which comes by nature. A
name is not whatever people call a thing by agreement, just a piece of their
own voice applied to the thing, but there is a kind of inherent correctness
(orthoteta tina ton onomaton pephukenai) which is the same for all men, both
Greeks and foreigners." Similarly Lucretius, a thoughtful and pragmatic
investigator, rejected the arbitrariness of the origin of words:"putare
aliquem tum nomina distribuisse desiperest. Nam cur hic posset cuncta notare
vocibus et varios sonitus emittere linguae tempore eodem alii id non quisse
putentur"(5: 1040-1045) - that is, people who think that some individual
could, by himself, have invented words arbitrarily are talking nonsense.
The tradition that words symbolise their meanings has continued over the
centuries. The polymath President De Brosses in the 18th century (the
correspondent and opponent of Voltaire) argued for the physiological origin
of words: "il y a de certains mouvements des organes appropriées à
désigner une certaine classe de choses de même espéce ou de
même qualité." In the 19th century the reality of the expressiveness
of words was championed by Humboldt in Germany, and later by Grammont(1901)
in France. Humboldt(1836) was certain that a connection between the sound of
a word and its meaning exists; he distinguished between onomatopoeia and sound
symbolism. The sound was not, in his view, a directly imitative sign but a
sign which indicated a quality which the sign and the object have in common;
to designate objects, language selected sounds which partly independently and
partly in comparison with others produce an impression which to the ear is
similar to that which the object makes upon the mind. Humboldt said that this
kind of sign process (based upon the particular meaning of each individual
letter and whole groups of letters) had undoubtedly exercised a prevailing,
perhaps even exclusive, influence on primitive word formation resulting in a
certain likeness of word-formation throughout all languages.
Otto Jespersen(1922) discussed at length the evidence for sound symbolism
and concluded that it should be seen not simply as a force that influenced the
initial formation of language but as one operating continually to make the
words used more appropriate to their sense, that is, sound symbolism is a
reality in the modern use and development of language. "Is there really much
more logic in the opposite extreme which denies any kind of sound symbolism
(apart from the small class of evident echoisms and 'onomatopoeia') and sees
in our words only a collection of accidental and irrational associations of
sound and meaning? .. Sounds may in some cases be symbolic of their sense even
if they are not so in all words... There is no denying that there are words
which we feel instinctively to be adequate to express the ideas they stand
for."(397-398). He directly criticised Saussure's approach: "De Saussure gives
as one of the main principles of our science that the tie between sound and
sense is arbitrary and rather motiveless.. and to those that would object that
onomatopoeic words are not arbitrary, he says that 'they are never organic
elements of a linguistic system' ... Here we see one of the characteristics
of modern linguistic science; it is so preoccupied with etymology that it pays
much more attention to what words have come from than to what they have come
to be .. Though some echo words may be very old, the great majority are not
.. In the course of time, languages grow richer and richer in symbolic words
.. Sound symbolism, we may say, makes some words much more fit to survive ..
Echoism and related phenomena - these forces are vital to languages as we
observe them day by day".(408-411)
Hormann, a more recent writer on psycholinguistics, quotes Stenzel who
emphasised "the belief, deeply rooted in our natural feeling for language,
that meaning lies directly in the sound of words; this belief is sustained by
a peculiar feeling that it is self-evident, which certainly constitutes a very
important experience in the mother-tongue and in any other language of which
we have a reasonable understanding."(Hormann 1971: 215)
For this 'important experience in the mother-tongue', the results of
Piagetian research seem relevant (though much neglected). Piaget and his
assistants found that young children uniformly say that words are derived
directly from the objects to which they relate. These findings were in
agreement with what Piaget termed well-known theories according to which to
a child's eye every object seems to possess a necessary and absolute name, a
part of the object's very nature; children believe that they are not taught
words for common things - the words originate within the child itself.
Children's ideas of this kind were, Piaget thought, evidence of their lack of
insight and understanding; they go on taking this sort of view until they have
had several years of formal schooling and reach the age of about eleven when
they come to accept that words are arbitrary and conventional. Piaget of
course accepted the linguistic orthodoxy unquestioningly; he did not seek
further for an explanation of the surprising uniformity with which children
perceive a natural link between word and meaning, merely commenting: "This
inability to dissociate names from things is very curious"(1973: 83). Perhaps
it is more than curious. 'Out of the mouths of babes' there may be something
which linguists ought to consider.
In spite of the accumulated evidence for sound symbolism, the unquestioning
attachment of most linguists (and researchers in other disciplines) to the
Saussurean dogma is puzzling. Perhaps Peterfalvi was not far from the truth:
"Pourquoi est-il important pour la linguistique contemporaine que le signe
linguistique soit arbitraire? .. Si en effet on partait du principe
générale que le signifiant et le signifié d'un signe linguistique
sont unis par des liens fondés sur l'analogie ou l'isomorphisme, toute
l'analyse des langues menée à bien par les linguistes (à commencer
par l'analyse phonologique) serait impossible sous sa forme actuelle"(1970:
77).
Most people probably have little idea of the weight of material bearing on
sound symbolism and the natural expressiveness of words. The list of
references for this paper(a partial bibliography for sound symbolism) gives
some idea of the continuity of commentary and research and the range of
languages and experimental work involved.
The case for sound symbolism, its character, does not, of course, depend
simply on authorities of the past. Since the 1920's and 1930's there has been
a very considerable volume of increasingly sophisticated experiment to test
and delimit the functioning of sound symbolism in modern languages. Some of
the research related to what was described as 'phonetic symbolism', that is,
the extent to which individual speech-sounds, phonemes, carried specific
meanings; other research related to the appropriateness of words as a whole
- 'morphosymbolism' (to adopt the term used by Malkiel(1978). The research can
be divided, with some overlapping, into several categories:
Sound symbolism within a single language. For example, experiment and
material indicating the extent to which in English individual phonemes are
symbolic or the sound-structures of words otherwise appear to be sound
symbolic or naturally appropriate to their meanings. Under this head, there
is evidence that in English (and in other languages) there are systematic
similarities between groups of words which refer to related percepts or have
related aspects of meaning not explainable in terms of orthodox principles of
etymology.
Sound symbolism between different languages, Typically, experiment under
this head assesses how far speakers of one particular language appear to be
able to use the sound-structure of words in another language (or in several
other languages) to arrive at the meaning of the words in the other language
(or languages). Under this head there is the wider question of the
universality of sound symbolism (or, more narrowly, of phonetic symbolism).
Also considered is evidence for sound symbolism in the form of correspondences
in unrelated languages between the sound-structures of words used for
particular percepts or ranges of percepts
Sound symbolism matching sounds or visual patterns with invented words This
is the kind of experimentation associated with Kohler(1929).
There has been extensive consideration of 'sound symbolism', the natural
expressiveness of word-sounds, in relation to the major European languages,
The phenomenon that words are felt to be naturally appropriate to their
meaning is as well-established for German, French and Spanish as it is for
English. The disagreement has been over how the feeling of the natural
suitability of words for their meanings is to be explained. In relation to the
English language, even linguists such as Bloomfield and Firth,who proclaim the
arbitrariness of language and deny the existence of sound symbolism, recognise
that particular feelings of appropriateness are associated with particular
words. Other authorities strongly support the reality of sound-symbolism in
the English language. Jespersen(1922) said that there was no denying that
there are words which we feel instinctively to be adequate to express the
ideas they stand for.
Roger Brown(1958), who dealt comprehensively with the issue of sound
symbolism, concluded that speakers of a given language have similar notions
of the semantic implications of various phonetic sequences.
Some of the most extensive work has been done in relation to German.
Humboldt(1836) quoted words like 'wolke' 'wirren' and 'wunsch' as expressing
the vacillating, wavering motion referred to. Hilmer(1914) compiled 170 pages
of word-lists of expressive words in German. This was followed up in a wider
context by other German researchers (described in the next section of this
paper). For French, Sauvageot(1964), whilst accepting Saussure's doctrine of
the arbitrariness of the sign, described the extent and importance of
onomatopoeia and expressive words. More recently, Peterfalvi(1970) assembled
evidence which convinced him of the reality of sound symbolism in French (and
more generally); he repeated experiments similar to those conducted earlier
by American and German researchers. In relation to Spanish, De Diego(1973)
concluded that all words in varying degrees have a sensory or emotive
value(69). As an example, he gave the Spanish name for the bird in English
called a 'wagtail':"in the word PIMPIM we have not an acoustic representation
of its song but an acoustic expression which translates a visual impression
of the rapidity of movement characteristic of the bird".(67)
Unlimited examples could be provided from other European languages and from
remoter languages for the existence of a felt relation between word-sounds and
word-meanings. FIRTH collected examples of expressive words in Norwegian,
Swedish and Dutch. In many examples, the syllables in a word apparently
correspond to the number of distinct elements in the sound, object or action,
for example, the word 'ongololo' meaning 'centipede' in Samoan (an example
given by Brown 1958). Sound symbolism seems to be as much or more of a reality
in remoter languages. Manchu is said to have been absolutely full of imitative
formations. There are many examples of sound symbolism in African languages;
in Ewe, high- tone words indicate small things and low-tone words large
things; in certain Sudanese languages high-tone words are used to express long
distances or high speed, and low-tone words to express proximity and slowness.
These examples are of particular interest as showing that sound symbolism is
a reality also for tonal languages. In Chinese, it is not irrelevant, in
considering visual contour as a foundation for the natural feeling of words,
that many of the Chinese classifiers (words indicating the category to which
an object belongs) are based on shape; there are, for example, classifying
particles which indicate long, flat and round objects, containers, pairs and
sets (curiously similar to classifiers used in some American Indian
languages). Studies of sound symbolism in a number of other languages are
listed in the bibliography e.g. Korean (Martin 1962, Kim 1977), Chinese
(Karlgren 1962), Japanese and Hindi (Koriat/Levy 1977), Semai (Diffloth 1976),
Bini (Wescott 1973), Yuman (Langdon 1971), Coeur D'Alene (Reichard 1945),
Azerbaijani (Householder 1962), N.W. American Indian (Haas 1970), Hungarian
(Allport 1935) and various West African languages (Samarin 1967).
Jakobson/Waugh(1987) refer also to studies of sound symbolism in Siouan and
Dakota.
Research within single languages has cast light on the issue of 'phonetic'
symbolism. Sapir(1929), on the basis of his experiment using two invented
words MAL and MIL which subjects were asked to identify with 'a large table'
or 'a small table', raised the issue whether phonemes in isolation are
symbolic, for example, of differing size. Newman(1933), who was a student of
Sapir's tested this for English by listing all words related to size, about
500. Comparing the small words with the large, he found no significant
difference in the size implications of the vowels used, that is, no
confirmation in natural language of the results found by Sapir. Roger
Brown(1958) independently did a similar study and also found no evidence of
symbolic representation of magnitude by the differentiated use of vowels. This
seems very likely. Consider in English, for example, the words BIG and SMALL,
MIGHTY and MITE. The conclusion seems unavoidable that the symbolic character
is dependent on the whole word and not on any single speech-sound considered
in isolation; if two words differ in only a single speech-sound, then the
symbolic character may change but this does mean that in all words containing
this opposition, the difference in symbolic effect will be the same.
Many words, in English and other languages, which are similar in the sounds
going to form them, derive their similarity from etymologically standard
processes of word-formation and word- development. This is true of the
conjugation and declension of words in inflected languages, of the formation
of comparatives or plurals in English and other languages, of the composition
of new words by the addition of prefixes or suffixes and so on. This kind of
resemblance between words, in a systematic way, is at the same time taken for
granted and fully natural. The more interesting kind of systematic resemblance
is where words have sounds and meanings which resemble one another but
etymologically the words are judged not to be related or derived from one
another by any standard process of composition, prefixing etc. This is a
phenomenon which has been observed in English and other languages and has been
commented on, as an unexplained curiosity, by a number of linguists and
others. Tylor(1871), the anthropologist, remarked on the way in which words,
whilst preserving so to speak the same skeleton, may be made to follow the
variation of sound, of force, of duration, which an imitative group will
show:- CRICK CREAK CRACK CRUSH CRUNCH CRAUNCH SCRUNCH SCRAUNCH. Firth(1937),
whilst disbelieving in sound symnbolism, assembled large collections of
symbolic words and emphasised the systematic way they may be related to each
other, quite separately from any etymological links; he acknowledged that we
are appreciably affected by initial and final phoneme groups not ordinarily
recognised as having any function. "Consider the following English words:
SLACK SLOUCH SLUDGE SLIME SLOSH SLASH SLOPPY SLUG SLUGGARD SLATTERN SLUT SLANG
SLY SLITHER SLOW SLOTH SLEEPY SLEET SLIP SLIPSHOD SLOPE SLIT SLAY SLEEK SLANT
SLOVENLY SLAB SLAP SLOUGH SLUM SLUMP SLOBBER SLAVER SLUR SLOG SLATE ... A
group of words such as the above has a cumulative suggestive value that cannot
be overlooked in any consideration of our habits of speech. All the above
words are in varying degrees pejorative".(Firth 1964: 184)
In English, there are many similar groupings of words where there is some
underlying resemblance of meaning related to the surface resemblance of the
sounds forming the words. Bloomfield(1933) quoted a number of these: examples
are such groups as: FIRE FLAME FLARE FLASH FLICKER POINT POKE PIKE PEG PEAK
PIERCE PRICK PROD PROBE PRONG HIT HACK HEW HATCHET HASH THROW THRUST THRASH
THWACK THWART THUMP THROTTLE SWEEP SWAY SWING SWIRL SWERVE SWOOP SWISH SWITCH
SWAT SWIPE SWAB WAG WAGGLE WEAVE WOBBLE WANDER WONDER WADDLE WAVER WAVE. The
felt resemblances between these sets of words is apparent and must derive from
symbolism in the sounds used - though not necessarily just from the initial
letters of the words since one can easily find examples of other words with
the same initial letters but belonging to completely different categories of
meaning; the resemblance seems to derive from the whole structure of the words
in each group.
Despite the examples he gave of expressive groups of words, Firth, as
already noted, explained them as simply the result of habit - but even in his
own terms, the question arises whether there is some universal or
physiological basis for these habits, for the preferences which people
demonstrate in their formation of words for particular sounds. There is no
necessary conflict between saying that a particular mode of behaviour, in
language or otherwise, is habitual and yet at the same time has a biological
or physiological basis. Firth drew attention to the existence of parallel
groups of expressive words in other languages. It is surprising that he did
not feel it necessary to consider more closely how it is, if these are purely
cultural phonaesthetic habits, they should be shared not only by speakers of
the same language but by speakers of other distinct languages. The parallel
development of similar phonetic habits in other communities makes it doubtful
whether a purely cultural explanation is adequate.
Jespersen(1922) also presented detailed material bearing on sound
symbolism: "the simplest case is the direct imitation of the sound: thus CLINK
... SPLASH ... BLEAT .. SNORT .. GRUNT ... But as our speech organs are not
capable of giving a perfect imitation of all 'unarticulated' sound, the choice
of speech- sounds is to a certain extent accidental and different nations have
chosen different combinations, more or less conventionalised, for the same
sounds, thus COCK-A-DOODLE-DO ... French COQUELICO .. and for whisper, French
CHUCHOTER Spanish SUSURAR .. Next the echoic word designates the being that
produces the sound (PEEWIT etc). Thirdly, as sound is always produced by some
movement and is nothing but the impression which that movement makes on the
ear, it is quite natural that movement itself may be expressed by the word for
its sound: the two are in fact inseparable. Note for example such verbs as
BUBBLE SPLASH CLASH CRACK PECK . Then we have words expressive of such
movements as are not to the same extent characterised by large sounds; thus
a great many words beginning with L combinations FL: FLOW ... SL: SLIDE ...
SLIP ...GL: GLIDE . Sound and sight may originally have been combined in such
expressions for an uncertain walk such as TOTTER DODDER .. but in cases of
this kind, the audible element may be wanting and the word may come to be felt
as symbolic of the movement as such. This is also the case with many
expressions for the sudden rapid movement by which we take hold of something;
as a short vowel suddenly interrupted by a stopped consonant serves to express
the sound produced by a very rapid striking movement (PAT TAP ..). Similar
sound combinations occur frequently for the more or less noiseless seizing of
a thing ... SNAP ... CATCH .. There is also a natural connection between the
action and the sound in the word TOT TICKLE (Latin: TITILLARE). There is some
more or less obvious association of what is only visible with some sound or
sounds ... We may also think of the word ZIGZAG as denoting movement in
alternate turns here and there"(Jespersen 1922:Chapter XX)
The distinction between the lists of expressive words presented by Firth
and those presented by Jespersen is that whereas Firth did not attempt to
explain why the particular sounds should have been chosen, Jespersen looked
for a systematic relation between the particular sounds composing expressive
words and the action, sound, perception etc. to which the word refers. He was
beginning to sketch out a detailed system of sound/meaning correspondences.
This systematic relation of sound and meaning was developed further by a
linguist opposed to the idea that there is any natural relation of sound and
meaning, Bloomfield(1933) pointed out that English is especially rich in a
type of intense forms, the symbolic forms which have a connotation of somehow
illustrating the meaning more immediately than do ordinary speech-forms. "The
explanation is a matter of grammatical structure ... to the speaker it seems
as if the sounds were especially suited to the meaning". Bloomfield's promised
explanation of symbolic forms in terms of grammatical structure never really
arrived. The nearest he came to it was in discussing the concept of roots
underlying vocabulary: "Primary words that do not contain any affix-like
constituents (e.g. BOY RUN RED) are classed as primary root-words..(240) A
root may appear in only one primary word, as is the case with ... MAN BOY CUT
RED ... or it may appear in a whole series of primary words ...(241) In the
Germanic languages, modification of the root occurs in words of symbolic
connotation as FLAP FLIP FLOP. If we take FLAP as the basic form of this root,
we shall describe FLIP FLOP as derivatives ...(242) However we find
clearly-marked phonetic- semantic resemblances between elements which we view
as different roots ... [In English symbolic word] we can distinguish, with
varying degrees of clearness, and with doubtful cases on the borderline, a
system of initial and final root-forming morphemes of vague signification. It
is plain that the intense symbolic connotation is associated with this
structure."(244-245)
This is a far from clear account of how the expressiveness of symbolic
forms is explained as a matter of grammatical structure. If in fact the
primary roots had any independent validity, if the so-called root-forming
morphemes were the product of some grammatical necessity, he might have an
adequate explanation - but his account was undermined by the admission that
the roots have no particular historical reality: "Now and then one still hears
the claim that the roots which we set up must once upon a time have been
spoken as independent words. The reader needs scarcely to be told that this
is utterly unjustified; the roots are merely units of partial resemblance
between words".(240) This amounts to no more than saying that systematic
resemblances can be observed between words which are said to be symbolic or
expressive. It says nothing about the origin of the expressiveness.
What has been quoted from Firth, Bloomfield and Jespersen represents an
earlier stage of discussion of sound symbolism, based on rather scattered
observation of apparent relations between sounds and meanings. More recently,
there has been a more experimental and quantitative approach. The
experimentation has been concerned with the different types of sound symbolism
which may exist, symbolism of whole words (of the kind that Jespersen and
Firth largely considered) and symbolism inherent in clusters of speech-sounds
(as considered by Bloomfield) or in individual speech-sounds, consonants or
vowels (as studied in Sapir's pioneering experiments). The research has not
been confined to sound symbolism as perceived by English-speakers but has
provided evidence for sound symbolism as a force operating in other language
communities. The experiments counter the criticism that apparent
appropriateness of sounds and meanings in any single language such as English
may be a peculiarity of that language or in any event may simply show that
single language communities tend (as Firth argued) to develop habits of
conventional origin in the sounds they use for particular clusters of ideas,
that sound symbolism is cultural rather than natural.
There has been as much, if not more, research into the extent to which
cross-linguistic sound symbolism is a reality i.e. that speakers of one
language can appreciate the expressive force of words in another language
(possibly one not at all known to them). There seems no doubt that
sound-symbolism does extend across languages but it is unsettled how far this
is universally true or whether there are some languages or groups of languages
for which the expressiveness of individual words in the languages cannot be
appreciated by members of other language-communities. Certainly, experiment
has shown cross-linguistic symbolism between a number of completely unrelated
languages but some experiments involving Chinese (and other tonal languages)
have been unsuccessful or unconvincing.
The sequence of experiments has developed consistently towards greater and
greater rigour. At first experimental subjects were asked simply to say
whether a selection of words drawn from various foreign languages sounded
appropriate or not to their meanings; though the result was that the subjects
were able to judge the appropriateness of the words, the experiment was not
conclusive because it might have been biased by the selection of words by the
experimenter. At the next stage, the experiment took the form (devised by
Tsuru) of presenting 36 pairs of opposite words in Japanese (meaning
'hot-cold' and so on) to subjects with no knowledge of Japanese and asking
them to match the Japanese words with the corresponding English words; the
words were successfully matched more frequently than could result purely from
chance and this finding suggested that the form or the sound of the Japanese
word must give some clue to the meaning. It was then argued that the Japanese
experimenter might by his selection of pairs of opposite words have
unconsciously biased the result; to eliminate unconscious bias in a new series
of experiments the pairs of opposite words in Japanese were translated into
Hungarian and Polish; the subjects taking part in these new experiments did
not, of course, speak or know Hungarian, Polish or Japanese but again the
result was that the foreign words were matched with the corresponding English
words more frequently than, statistically, could be explained as resulting
from pure chance. The same sort of experiment was repeated with Czech, Hindi,
Croatian and Hebrew and in each case added to the cumulative evidence for the
existence of cross-linguistic symbolism between non-tonal languages.
Experiment on somewhat different lines (Ertel/Dorst 1965) found evidence for
expressive sound symbolism between languages for 25 languages.
What follows is a summary account of some of the more significant pieces
of research (drawing where necessary on discussion of some of these
experiments in Brown 1958, Hormann 1971, Peterfalvi 1970 and Jakobson/Waugh
1987):
Muller(1935) attempted to meet the difficulty that sound symbolism of
natural words might be peculiar to a single language, a cultural artefact, by
testing with children whether words drawn from remote languages (Samoan,
Bantu, Eskimo) were felt to be appropriate. He chose such words as TUMBA
(meaning swelling) and ONGOLOLO (centipede) where the appropriateness seemed
apparent - but his results could have been vitiated by unconsciously biassed
selection of the words used.
Tsuru/Fries(1935} followed a different plan which became the model for much
subsequent experimentation. Tsuru compiled a list of 36 pairs of Japanese
antonyms ('hot-cold' 'high-low' etc) and used as experimental subjects 57
native English-speakers with no knowledge of Japanese. The subjects were asked
to match the English pairs of antonyms (spoken and written in Romanised form).
A chance result would have been that they should guess correctly in 50% of the
cases; they guessed correctly significantly more often than this and therefore
must have been offered some clue to the right answers by the form or sound of
the Japanese words. These results suggested (since Japanese is taken to be a
language unrelated to English) that they must have been relying on some
universal phonetic symbolism - not simply a conventional association of sound
and meaning. Roger Brown(1958) commented that even this experiment is subject
to the criticism that there may have been selection by the Japanese
experimenter of words which happened to bear some relation to the
corresponding English forms., or that there may in any case be coincidences
between forms in Japanese and English which would lead to apparently better
than chance results.
Allport(1935) sought to evade these criticisms, in experiment on similar
lines to Tsuru, by translating Tsuru's set of antonyms into Hungarian
(unrelated to Japanese or English) so that any unconscious selection would be
nullified, Nevertheless, the Hungarian words were guessed by the experimental
subjects with more than chance success. The experiment was repeated on the
same pattern by Rich(1953) with pairs of Japanese and Polish words and again
resulted in correct answers significantly above chance.
Brown/Black/Horowitz(1955) did an experiment with pairs of words translated
into Chinese, Czech and Hindi which 85 experimental subjects had to guess. The
results again were above chance. Roger Brown commented on these experiments
that English-speaking subjects matching words with the Japanese, Hungarian,
Chinese, Czech, Hindi and Croatian languages, were always right more than half
the time, which suggests that there are resemblances between sound and meaning
apparent to men everywhere and that these have played some part in the
development of all natural languages with the result that semantic rules in
totally unfamiliar languages do not seem to us to be quite arbitrary.
Brown/Black repeated the experiments with a group of Chinese- speakers. The
results were somewhat discouraging. The Chinese matching words with Hindi and
Czech, though still producing results somewhat above chance, did less well
(particularly for Czech) than English-speakers. In particular, on the MAL/MIL
contrast which was introduced into the test, the Chinese responded at the
chance level. these results meant that Brown had to reach a much more
tentative conclusion about universal phonetic symbolism than he had earlier
proposed: "Totally problematical is the existence of a universal human
phonetic symbolism. The phonetic symbolism of the English speaking community
may be entirely a result of similar linguistic training... [The Chinese
experiment] has shown that the answer to the questions of universal phonetic
symbolism will not be easily obtained and when obtained is not likely to be
a simple one. There may after all be some associations of sound and meaning
that are universally known and others that are a cultural product"(Brown
1958:) On Brown's rather negative conclusion, one can comment that it is
apparently only in relation to Chinese that the matching of pairs of words
from different languages was less satisfactory. It may be relevant to note
that for non-tonal languages, the appropriateness of sounds to meanings of
words involves a relationship with the phonemes which form the common basis
of these languages. In the case of tonal languages, like Chinese, a quite
different principle is found to convey meaning, that is, the pattern of pitch
of the voice in the speaking of the word. It would not be surprising if
speakers of non-tonal languages should find more difficulty in observing the
sound- appropriateness of words in tonal languages or if speakers of tonal
languages found more difficulty in judging the phonetic appropriateness of
words from non-tonal languages.
Maltzmann/Morrisett/Brooks(1956) argued that if the matching of
English/Japanese and English/Croatian by English-speaking subjects succeeds
with more than chance probability and this is really the result of universal
phonetic symbolism, then it should not matter whether the experimental
subjects know either of the two languages from which the words are drawn which
are to be matched. It should therefore be possible to match the words of two
languages unknown to the experimental subjects. However the experiment - with
American subjects matching Croatian and Japanese word lists - produced results
not above the chance level. The difference from the earlier successful
experiments was
that the subjects were not matching pairs of words but single words from each
language.
Brackbill/Little(1957) Six groups of 40 English-speaking subjects were
asked to judge equivalences of meaning for 3 sets of 50 pairs of words. The
words were a random sample of high- frequency concepts and the three sets were
pairs of words in English/Chinese, English/Japanese, English/Hebrew,
Chinese/Hebrew. The subjects were able to give English equivalents of Hebrew
words and to pair Japanese/Chinese and Japanese/Hebrew words at better than
chance level. However, in pairing Chinese/Hebrew, correct guesses were
significantly below chance. The authors interpreted the results of the study
as contrary to the hypothesis of a universal phonetic symbolism: they did not
find that subjects were able to guess the English meanings of Chinese words
significantly above chance. But the process of matching pairs was facilitated
by marked contrasts of meaning. They concluded that (apart from the
Chinese/Hebrew failure) non-cognate languages may employ similar patterns of
sounds (and length of words) to designate similar meanings - at least among
frequently used words.
Miron(1961) undertook a cross-linguistic investigation of phonetic
symbolism using invented words. Such invented words have expressive symbolic
value according to their inherent phonetic content and not to any meanings
they may have via real-word associates. These affective meanings were found
to bear consistent lawful relations to the phonetic properties of sounds. He
concluded that the laws governing phonetic symbolism may be of a universal
character.
Taylor/Taylor(1962) studied phonetic symbolism between unrelated languages.
Phonetic symbolism occurred under all conditions in the three experiments they
conducted but the symbolism was not universal; their results pointed to
language-dependent mechanisms - symbolism was not identical in the different
languages used. So, for example, they found that in Korean the initial letters
T and P in single syllable words are associated with very big magnitudes,
whilst they are associated with very small magnitudes in English. The
languages they used, English, Japanese, Korean and Tamil were assumed to be
historically unrelated.
Weiss(1964) The process of matching words from different languages is
facilitated if the context is restricted. If for example it is known that the
topic is 'tables' correct matching is facilitated. The evidence is that the
phonetic symbolism is not based on similarity of initial consonants.
Johnson/Suzuki/Ohls(1964) Certain letters and letter combinations occur
more often than would be expected by chance in affectively pleasant words
while others are over-represented in unpleasant words. Artificial words were
constructed using these letters and combinations of letters.After hearing the
invented words, the subjects were asked to match English words expressing
pleasant or unpleasant feelings, attitudes etc. with one or other of two
invented words. The appropriate matches were made significantly more often
than chance expectancy.The experimenters concluded that their findings
supported the notion that phonetic symbolism exists.
Aztet(1965) An experiment was run using 60 native speakers of the Navajo
language who were asked to match Navajo antonyms with their Chinese and Hindi
equivalents. The results were negative. Examples of the antonyms used:
Beautiful ugly, Bright dark, Up down, Wet dry, Fast slow, Big Little, High
low, Cool warm, Push pull, Thin fat. It is uncertain what weight should be
attached to the results of this experiment. Navajo is also a tonal language
but in a way very different from tonality in Chinese.
Ertel/Dorst(1965) using an approach similar to that of Weiss found
confirmation for expressive sound symbolism in twenty five languages. They
asked native speakers to make tape recordings of terms of emotion in the
different languages. The subjects who listened to the tape recordings had to
decide whether the sound sequences had a 'positive' aspect (good, happy etc)
or a 'negative' aspect (bad, sad etc) i.e. a decision on feeling tone. Such
matching succeeded in all languages with a probability in excess of chance.
Taylor(1965) Experiments matching antonyms do not answer the fundamental
question, what sound has what meaning. For example, the Japanese words AKA
'red' MIDORI 'green' show some common features with the English words but
which, if any, of these common features is identified with 'greenness' or
'redness'? The concept of phonetic symbolism has to be modified. A new
hypothesis must be found that accounts not only for the fact that people
associate certain sounds with certain meanings, but also the fact that people
speaking different languages associate the same sounds with different
meanings.
Peterfalvi(1970) repeated with French language-speakers experimental work
which previously had been carried out in the United States and Germany. The
experimental results suggested that the symbolism of a sequence of phonemes
derives equally from the consonants and the vowels although the part played
by the vowels is better established and more constant. Phonetic symbolism (or
at least the feeling that it exists) is not restricted to artificial words
invented for the purpose. The matching of words referring to movement is more
adequate (in terms of the relation of sound to meaning) than for visual words.
There is correspondence between the physical and symbolic character of sounds
for three categories: between sounds and meanings, between visual patterns and
meanings and between sounds and visual patterns.
Koriat/Levy(1977) examined the symbolic implications of vowels in Japanese
and Hindi. They found that the sound-patterns carried cross-culturally
consistent symbolic connotations.
Though the evidence is strong, on the basis of the research, for the view
that sound symbolism is a reality within individual languages and for a sound
symbolism extended to cover non-cognate languages (but not necessarily all
languages - tonal languages such as Chinese look to be exceptions), little
explanation is offered of the natural basis for phonetic symbolism (assuming
that the cross-linguistic results rule out any simple cultural explanation).
If one examines the words in a large number of languages for a range of
commonly encountered objects, actions or qualities (parts of the body,
colours, simple actions, air, water, earth, pronouns, demonstratives), one
finds that resemblances of sound and meaning spread across many languages,
related and unrelated, including languages which geographically and in terms
of language family are extremely remote from each other. The resemblances go
beyond anything that can plausibly be explained as the result of chance or
coincidence. Linguists have often noted the extent of these surprising
resemblances, quoting particularly notorious examples such as 'have' in
English and 'habere' in Latin (which etymologists say are unrelated to each
other), 'path' and 'bad' in English and 'path' and 'bad' in Persian (also said
to be unrelated), 'fire' and 'feuer' in English and German which are said to
be unrelated to 'feu' in French, 'day' and 'dies' in Latin (not related),
'whole' and 'holos' in Greek (meaning 'whole' but unrelated to the English
word).
Comparative linguists have reacted to these resemblances in two opposed
ways: a few have argued that the extensive resemblances between distant
languages in vocabulary can only be explained by assuming that all or nearly
all languages, at some great distance in time, were related to a single parent
language (Swadesh built up his procedure of glottochronology on the basis that
the degree of resemblance between the words in different languages could be
used to calculate how many centuries or thousands of years earlier the
different languages developed from a common base). Other linguists, the
orthodox majority, dismiss any idea that all languages are related or derived
from a single proto-language. Over the centuries there has been a very great
deal of effort put into looking for resemblances between particular languages
(to suggest that Indo-European languages are related to Hebrew, or Basque to
Georgian or to any number of other languages) and also some effort, though on
a smaller scale, to support the contention that all languages are related and
derive from one primeval language. Comparative linguists have not been
convinced because they argue that similarity of vocabulary by itself proves
nothing about the family relation of languages; what matters is systematic
structural relationship.
Whether or not lexical resemblances indicate relationship, the fact remains
that the resemblances do really exist and call for some explanation. A
straightforward approach to the problem is to prepare a list of words
referring to a range of ordinary objects, actions, qualities and relations,
chosen on the basis that they are words most unlikely to have been borrowed
into English and that for the most part they are likely to be acquired by
children from direct experience rather than by explanation and instruction.
This list of (English) words can then be set in parallel with the equivalent
words in an extensive range of other languages (including particularly
languages unrelated in any way to English). One can then examine what in fact
is the extent of resemblance.how far resemblance is confined to related
languages and how far it extends to unrelated languages and whether the words
in other languages listed for a particular object etc. resemble one another
even if they do not resemble the word found in English.
When a list prepared in this way (for some 40 objects and 23 languages) was
examined, striking resemblances between remote languages were apparent. A few
examples:
(1)CRAB: out of 23 words for 'crab', 14 began with K or C or had K as a
prominent sound in the word; for the remainder of the words in the list (that
is referring to objects etc. other than 'crab'), K as an initial sound or as
a prominent sound was rare; similarities between some individual unrelated
languages for 'crab' were Korean 'ke', Swahili 'kaa', Japanese 'kani', Telegu
'kappu', Latin 'cancer' Malayan 'kepiting'.
(2)CUT: out of 23 words for 'cut', 15 began with K (or C) or had K as a
prominent sound ('cut' was the only other word, besides 'crab', out of the
list of 40 to have K (or hard C) as an initial sound). Similarities between
unrelated languages were Arabic 'kata', Chinese 'ko', Telegu 'koyu', Japanese
'kiru', Greek 'keiro', Hebrew 'karat', Spanish 'cortar'.
(3)LICK: 14 of the words began with L or had L as a prominent sound.
Similarities: Hebrew 'likek', Basque 'milikatu', Greek 'likhmadzo', Hungarian
'nyal', Latin 'lingo' or 'lambo', Swahili 'lamba' (one Amerindian language
had as its word for 'lick ' the word 'lambi').
(4)NAME: 12 of the words began with N whilst a further 8 out of the 23 had
N or M as a prominent sound. Similarities: German 'name', Japanese 'namae',
Turkish 'nam', Malay 'nama', Finnish 'nimi', (an Amerindian language had
'nami' and Chinese has 'ming').
(5)SAME: Resemblances: Finnish 'sama', Malay 'sama', Arabic 'sawa', Telegu
'sawa', Lozi 'swana', and Russian 'samyi'.
This is only a very small sample of resemblances to show the basis for the
general conclusion reached that in the case of a good number of words for
common objects etc. (where borrowing between languages or language families
is unlikely) there are resemblances even between remote languages which can
hardly be explained as the result of coincidence. Cross-language sound
symbolism seems a more likely explanation.
If sound symbolism is operating in this way, then it may also explain the
parallelisms between sound and meaning in groups of words for related percepts
etc. In English, as mentioned earlier, there are groups of what Bloomfield
described as intense forms, words with similar initial sound-structures which
share some aspect of meaning although etymologically they are unrelated. The
following matches one of these groups of English words with groups of words
with similar meanings in Malay and French:
....Malay...........English........French
....KELEPOK.........CLAP...........CLAQUER
....KUKU............CLAW...........GRIFFE
....KEPITAN.........CLASP..........AGRAFER
....KEPITING........CRAB...........CRABE
....KETAM...........CLAMP..........CRAMPON
....KERKAH..........CRUNCH.........CROQUER
....KUMPUL..........CLUSTER........GRAPPE
....GENGGAMAN.......GRASP..........AGRIPPER
....GILING..........GRIND..........GRINCER
....KERTIK..........CLICK..........CLIQUETER
....KERINCHING......CLATTER........CLAQUER
....GERGAU..........SCRATCH........GRATTER
....KISUT...........CRINKLE........GRIGNER
....MENGGERUTU......GRUMBLE........GROGNER
It appears that Malay and French form imitative and expressive words for
these related meanings through the use of sound- sequences similar to those
familiar in English.
The following account draws on Roger Brown's(1958) discussion of these
forms of sound symbolism. Onomatopoeia in its limited sense (imitation of
natural sounds) is a familiar and well- recorded form of sound symbolism:
Wissemann(1954) conducted an experiment to investigate the principles on
which onomatopoeic words are formed. The pattern of the experiment was as
follows: The subjects were German-speakers. They were asked to listen to 14
different artificial noises. Example: the noise of a wooden ball rolling down
a plywood board to drop into a metal box. For each of the noises they were
asked to invent an appropriate new word or to select an appropriate word from
a list of words invented by the experimenter. In the outcome, the length of
the words chosen or invented was found to be related systematically not to the
duration of the noise but to the number of distinct divisions in the noise.
Noises starting abruptly were matched with words starting with a consonant
such as P T K; a noise beginning gradually was named by a word beginning with
a consonant such as S or Z. Thus initial speech- sounds of onomatopoeic words
reproduced the stimulus gradients of the noises to which the words referred.
Tongue position in articulation was more important for phonetic symbolism than
lip position. At the conclusion of the experiment, the subjects were asked to
explain the basis on which they had chosen the onomatopoeic words. All of
them, without discussion or instruction, said they had used similar principles
in selecting the onomatopoeic words.
Wissemann's results were in line with what one might expect and with what
can be seen in studying familiar onomatopoeic words. Rather more interesting
and surprising has been experiment on the relation between visual shapes and
words chosen to match individual shapes. There seems evidence from the
experiments for a kind of visual onomatopoeia. Usnadze was perhaps the first
to explore this though the experiments of Sapir and Kohler are better known
and better tested.
Sapir(1929) An English-speaking subject is asked to consider the
appropriate name for each of two tables, one large and one small. The word for
one of the tables is MIL and for the other MAL. With five hundred subjects,
Sapir reported that some 80% thought that MAL represented the larger table and
MIL the smaller. Other researchers have repeated the experiment many times
since, with similar results, using subjects speaking different languages and
from countries with quite different cultures.
Newman(1933) extended Sapir's experimental pattern and was able to place
the vowels on a scale of magnitude from small to large. In general larger
magnitudes were associated by experimental subjects with a large oral cavity,
a low vocalic resonance and the tongue towards the back of the mouth. However,
as indicated earlier, Newman found no systematic confirmation for vowel-
symbolism as such in natural English words.
Usnadze(1924) conducted the earliest exploration of 'visual onomatopoeia'.
He presented his ten (German-speaking) subjects with a set of invented
'nonsense' drawings and asked them to select from a list of invented words
appropriate names for them. In some instances the drawing was reminiscent of
a familiar object and the subject chose an invented word similar to the
conventional name. In other cases the subject chose a name with the same
Gestalt or form as the picture. Roger Brown(1958), from whom this account is
drawn, says that Usnadze did not attempt to explain the basis of the
association between the words and the visual shapes. Brown suggested that the
number of syllables in the words might correspond to the number of perceptual
sub-wholes in the drawings. Usnadze's work has been continued by other
Georgian psychologists (Natadze 1966) and by Fox(1935).
Kohler(1929) devised an experiment on rather similar lines to investigate
the symbolic relation between visual patterns and the sound-structure of
words. He made use of two arbitrary visual shapes, one rounded and the other
angular and invented two words as names for them, TAKETE and MALUMA. Subjects
were asked to associate with each shape one of the invented words. The
overwhelming majority of subjects assigned MALUMA to the rounded shape and
TAKETE to the angular one. His experiment has been repeated many times in many
countries since then. The results have been equally striking and have been
taken as demonstrating a so far unexplained parallelism between visual and
auditory structures.
Whilst it is relatively easy to see how invented words might match invented
sound-sequences (on the lines of Wissemann's experiment), it is rather harder
to imagine the kind of relation that might exist between invented words and
visual shapes (the kind of experiment conducted by Kohler and Usnadze). The
following page illustrates what is involved. It shows Sapir's and Kohler's
material and also a set of six arbitrary visual patterns to be matched with
six invented word-forms. For the reader who wishes to attempt to identify the
word matching each particular visual shape, a few notes of guidance:
1. The invented words are in alphabetical order, that is, not placed
opposite the visual shapes to which they refer; 2. To judge the
appropriateness of a word to any shape, articulate the word. Do not just look
at the word or read it silently. Do not attempt only to match the spelling to
the shape. What matters is the pattern of movement of the mouth, tongue etc,
the feel of the word as it is spoken. 3. Consonants should be pronounced as
in English; vowels should be given standard values. 4.It may be helpful to use
gesture, that is, to match the contour of the visual shape by moving the arm.
As the gesture is made, consider the appropriateness of any particular word
to the particular shape.
The evidence for the reality of sound symbolism in various forms seems
strong. That it operates within any single language can hardly be doubted.
That it can operate between languages and language-communities to a
considerable extent also seems to be established by extensive research. The
existence of a universal sound-symbolism (that is, applying uniformly to all
languages) seems less certain - tonal languages seem to form a distinct group
from non-tonal languages in this respect. The operation of specific
consonantal or vowel sound symbolism (phonetic symbolism in the narrow sense)
has not been established; sound symbolism appears to be symbolism of the whole
word (morphosymbolism) rather than of the individual phoneme. It seems
probable that sound symbolism comprises not only traditional onomatopoeia
(words imitating natural sounds) but also visual and auditory onomatopoeia (a
relation between visual shapes, invented sound- patterns and invented words)
as well as a symbolism related to less easily defined qualities (pleasant and
unpleasant sensation, emotional values etc).
If sound symbolism is a reality, how is it to be explained? Most
researchers have felt the need for some explanation but have not been able to
suggest what form it might take. Hans Marchand(1959) devoted a detailed study
to symbolism in English word-formation but confessed himself at a loss to find
out what the symbolism is based upon. Peterfalvi noted that research had
established the facts of sound symbolism but without interpreting them.
Nevertheless, the explanations offered by those few authors who have
attempted to understand the basis of sound symbolism show remarkable
convergence. Jakobson/Waugh(1987) say that sound symbolism derives from an
inmost, natural similarity association between sound and meaning; sound
symbolism is an undeniably objective reality founded on association between
the different sensory modalities, particularly between vision and hearing.
De Diego(1973) Like other forms of gesture, articulatory gesticulation is
directed towards expressing reality. The sense of the appropriateness of a
word to its meaning is due to coincidence of the reality which it represents
with our own internal organisation. Sound symbolism is associated with the
interrelation of different modes of perception; stimulation of one form of
perception automatically activates other modes of perception.
Peterfalvi(1970) There is a specific psychological basis for sound
symbolism, Correspondence between the sound-structure of the word and its
meaning is an aspect of synaesthesia, derived from the generalisation to other
modalities of sensory stimuli in the particular modality to which a word
refers. The sound-meaning matching for words referring to movement is more
adequate than for visual words; a word which evokes impressions of movements
may be thought more appropriate because it triggers off mechanisms similar to
those which are involved in the actual source of sound symbolism. This seems
not far removed from Sokolov's(1972) discussion of the relation of speech and
thought (developing ideas originating with Sechenov). Sechenov stressed the
enormous importance of the 'muscle sense' in objective- pictorial and in
verbal-abstract thinking; owing to this 'muscle sense' (kinaesthetic
perception), various sensory impressions are integrated into one complex
whole.
These approaches fit well with the motor theory of language origin and
function. This stresses the necessarily close relation in the central nervous
system between motor control, perception in all its forms and language. Sound
symbolism - a feeling of a natural relation between the sound-structure and
meaning of words - is precisely what the motor theory would lead one to
expect. This is synaesthesia (including Sechenov's 'muscle-sense') given a
much more specific content and forming part of a larger theoretical system.
1. Evidence and experiment
2. Sound symbolism within a single language
3. Resemblance within a single language between etymologically unrelated
words with related meanings
4. Sound symbolism between languages
5. Resemblance between words for the same percepts in different languages
6. Sound symbolism matching sounds or visual shapes with invented
words
7. CONCLUSION: Explanations for sound symbolism